Naive Encodings of Transitivity within First-Order Logic
Published on
The transitive closure of a binary relation cannot, in general, be expressed in first-order logic (FO)
In Ray Reiter’s book “Knowledge in Action: Logical Foundations for Specifying and Implementing Dynamical Systems”, he goes over a typical naive encoding of transitivity in first-order logic and goes over a counter-example1.
Let $G$ be a binary relation that represents whether or not there is a direct edge between two nodes.
We want to axiomatize the transitive closure into the binary relation $T$. This means we need to have a formula that holds when we have a transitive closure, and does not hold when we do not.
A naive axiomatization is the following: $$ T(x, y) \iff G(x, y) \vee \exists z(G(x, z) \wedge T(z, y)) $$ Ray’s counter-example is the following. Consider the following valuation of $G$:
G: {(b, b)}
Now consider the following valuation of $T$:
T: {(b, a), (b, b)}
We falsely state that b
is connected to a
via transitive closure. If our axiomatization is sound, then it should be falsified.
$$
\begin{align*}
T(b, a) &\iff G(b, a) \vee \exists z (G(b, z) \wedge T(z, a)) \\
&\impliedby \bot \vee (G(b, b) \wedge T(b, a)) \\
&\impliedby \bot \vee (\top \wedge \top) \\
&\impliedby \top
\end{align*}
$$
However, the formula is satisfied! Therefore, this cannot be used to axiomatize transitive closure.
That’s the end of the original counter-example in the book. However, I thought it would be fun to extend the exercise.
The issue in the last example, is that we had a cycle in which we were able to define $T(b, a)$ in terms of $T(b, a)$. What if we add a constraint so that isn’t the case? $$ T(x, y) \iff G(x, y) \vee \exists z(z \ne x \wedge G(x, z) \wedge T(z, y)) $$ Does this new formula axiomatize transitive closure? The quote at the beginning begs to differ, so let’s find a counter-example!
Consider the following valuations for $G$ and $T$:
G: {(b, a), (a, b)}
T: {(b, c), (a, c)}
As before, this model should not have transitive closure. Let’s evaluate our modified formula. $$ \begin{align*} T(b, c) &\iff G(b, c) \vee \exists z (z \ne b \wedge G(b, z) \wedge T(z,c)) \\ &\impliedby \bot \vee (a \ne b \wedge G(b, a) \wedge T(a, c)) \\ &\impliedby \bot \vee (\top \wedge \top \wedge \top) \\ &\impliedby \top \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} T(a, c) &\iff G(a, c) \vee \exists z (G(a, z) \wedge T(z, c)) \\ &\impliedby G(a, c) \vee (b \ne a \wedge G(a, b) \wedge T(b, c)) \\ &\impliedby \bot \vee (\top \wedge \top \wedge \top) \\ &\impliedby \top \end{align*} $$
Here we can see that the above valuations depending on each other.
Wikipedia has a great article on transitive closure including a section on its use within logic and computational complexity.
(First-order Transitive-Closure Logic) FO(TC) is strictly more expressive than FO.
-
Unfortunately there was an errata in Example 2.1.1. The set
T
should be described as{(b, a), (b, b)}
instead of the typo{(a, b), (b, b)}
. Thanks James for noticing this! ↩︎